Bertrand Russell on Immortality, Why Religion Exists, and What “The Good Life” Really Means (2024)

Bertrand Russell on Immortality, Why Religion Exists, and What “The Good Life” Really Means (1)Bertrand Russell (May 18, 1872–February 2, 1970) is one of humanity’s most grounding yet elevating thinkers, his writing at once lucid and luminous. There is something almost prophetic in the way he bridges timelessness and timeliness in contemplating ideas urgently relevant to modern life a century earlier — from how boredom makes happiness possible to why science is the key to democracy. But nowhere does his genius shine more brilliantly than in What I Believe (public library).

Published in 1925, the book is a kind of catalog of hopes — a counterpoint to Russell’s Icarus, a catalog of fears released the previous year — exploring our place in the universe and our “possibilities in the way of achieving the good life.”

Bertrand Russell on Immortality, Why Religion Exists, and What “The Good Life” Really Means (2)

Russell writes in the preface:

In human affairs, we can see that there are forces making for happiness, and forces making for misery. We do not know which will prevail, but to act wisely we must be aware of both.

One of Russell’s most central points deals with our civilizational allergy to uncertainty, which we try to alleviate in ways that don’t serve the human spirit. Nearly a century before astrophysicist Marcelo Gleiser’s magnificent manifesto for mystery in the age of knowledge — and many decades before “wireless” came to mean what it means today, making the metaphor all the more prescient and apt — Russell writes:

It is difficult to imagine anything less interesting or more different from the passionate delights of incomplete discovery. It is like climbing a high mountain and finding nothing at the top except a restaurant where they sell ginger beer, surrounded by fog but equipped with wireless.

Long before modern neuroscience even existed, let alone knew what it now knows about why we have the thoughts we do — the subject of an excellent recent episode of the NPR’s Invisibilia — Russell points to the physical origins of what we often perceive as metaphysical reality:

What we call our “thoughts” seem to depend upon the organization of tracks in the brain in the same sort of way in which journeys depend upon roads and railways. The energy used in thinking seems to have a chemical origin; for instance, a deficiency of iodine will turn a clever man into an idiot. Mental phenomena seem to be bound up with material structure.

Nowhere, Russell argues, do our thought-fictions stand in starker contrast with physical reality than in religious mythology — and particularly in our longing for immortality which, despite a universe whose very nature contradicts the possibility, all major religions address with some version of a promise for eternal life. With his characteristic combination of cool lucidity and warm compassion for the human experience, Russell writes:

God and immortality … find no support in science… No doubt people will continue to entertain these beliefs, because they are pleasant, just as it is pleasant to think ourselves virtuous and our enemies wicked. But for my part I cannot see any ground for either.

And yet, noting that the existence or nonexistence of a god cannot be proven for it lies “outside the region of even probable knowledge,” he considers the special case of personal immortality, which “stands on a somewhat different footing” and in which “evidence either way is possible”:

Persons are part of the everyday world with which science is concerned, and the conditions which determine their existence are discoverable. A drop of water is not immortal; it can be resolved into oxygen and hydrogen. If, therefore, a drop of water were to maintain that it had a quality of aqueousness which would survive its dissolution we should be inclined to be skeptical. In like manner we know that the brain is not immortal, and that the organized energy of a living body becomes, as it were, demobilized at death, and therefore not available for collective action. All the evidence goes to show that what we regard as our mental life is bound up with brain structure and organized bodily energy. Therefore it is rational to suppose that mental life ceases when bodily life ceases. The argument is only one of probability, but it is as strong as those upon which most scientific conclusions are based.

But evidence, Russell points out, has little bearing on what we actually believe. (In the decades since, pioneering psychologist and Nobel laureate Daniel Kahneman has demonstrated that the confidence we have in our beliefs is no measure of their accuracy.) Noting that we simply desire to believe in immortality, Russell writes:

Believers in immortality will object to physiological arguments [against personal immortality] on the ground that soul and body are totally disparate, and that the soul is something quite other than its empirical manifestations through our bodily organs. I believe this to be a metaphysical superstition. Mind and matter alike are for certain purposes convenient terms, but are not ultimate realities. Electrons and protons, like the soul, are logical fictions; each is really a history, a series of events, not a single persistent entity. In the case of the soul, this is obvious from the facts of growth. Whoever considers conception, gestation, and infancy cannot seriously believe that the soul in any indivisible something, perfect and complete throughout this process. It is evident that it grows like the body, and that it derives both from the spermatozoon and from the ovum, so that it cannot be indivisible.

Long before the term “reductionism” would come to dismiss material answers to spiritual questions, Russell offers an elegant disclaimer:

This is not materialism: it is merely the recognition that everything interesting is a matter of organization, not of primal substance.

Our obsession with immortality, Russell contends, is rooted in our fear of death — a fear that, as Alan Watts has eloquently argued, is rather misplaced if we are to truly accept our participation in the cosmos. Russell writes:

Fear is the basis of religious dogma, as of so much else in human life. Fear of human beings, individually or collectively, dominates much of our social life, but it is fear of nature that gives rise to religion. The antithesis of mind and matter is … more or less illusory; but there is another antithesis which is more important — that, namely, between things that can be affected by our desires and things that cannot be so affected. The line between the two is neither sharp nor immutable — as science advances, more and more things are brought under human control. Nevertheless there remain things definitely on the other side. Among these are all the large facts of our world, the sort of facts that are dealt with by astronomy. It is only facts on or near the surface of the earth that we can, to some extent, mould to suit our desires. And even on the surface of the earth our powers are very limited. Above all, we cannot prevent death, although we can often delay it.

Religion is an attempt to overcome this antithesis. If the world is controlled by God, and God can be moved by prayer, we acquire a share in omnipotence… Belief in God … serves to humanize the world of nature, and to make men feel that physical forces are really their allies. In like manner immortality removes the terror from death. People who believe that when they die they will inherit eternal bliss may be expected to view death without horror, though, fortunately for medical men, this does not invariably happen. It does, however, soothe men’s fears somewhat even when it cannot allay them wholly.

In a sentiment of chilling prescience in the context of recent religiously-motivated atrocities, Russell adds:

Religion, since it has its source in terror, has dignified certain kinds of fear, and made people think them not disgraceful. In this it has done mankind a great disservice: all fear is bad.

Science, Russell suggests, offers the antidote to such terror — even if its findings are at first frightening as they challenge our existing beliefs, the way Galileo did. He captures this necessary discomfort beautifully:

Even if the open windows of science at first make us shiver after the cosy indoor warmth of traditional humanizing myths, in the end the fresh air brings vigor, and the great spaces have a splendor of their own.

But Russell’s most enduring point has to do with our beliefs about the nature of the universe in relation to us. More than eight decades before legendary graphic designer Milton Glaser’s exquisite proclamation — “If you perceive the universe as being a universe of abundance, then it will be. If you think of the universe as one of scarcity, then it will be.” — Russell writes:

Optimism and pessimism, as cosmic philosophies, show the same naïve humanism; the great world, so far as we know it from the philosophy of nature, is neither good nor bad, and is not concerned to make us happy or unhappy. All such philosophies spring from self-importance, and are best corrected by a little astronomy.

He admonishes against confusing “the philosophy of nature,” in which such neutrality is necessary, with “the philosophy of value,” which beckons us to create meaning by conferring human values upon the world:

Nature is only a part of what we can imagine; everything, real or imagined, can be appraised by us, and there is no outside standard to show that our valuation is wrong. We are ourselves the ultimate and irrefutable arbiters of value, and in the world of value Nature is only a part. Thus in this world we are greater than Nature. In the world of values, Nature in itself is neutral, neither good nor bad, deserving of neither admiration nor censure. It is we who create value and our desires which confer value… It is for us to determine the good life, not for Nature — not even for Nature personified as God.

Russell’s definition of that “good life” remains the simplest and most heartening one I’ve ever encountered:

The good life is one inspired by love and guided by knowledge.

Knowledge and love are both indefinitely extensible; therefore, however good a life may be, a better life can be imagined. Neither love without knowledge, nor knowledge without love can produce a good life.

What I Believe is a remarkably prescient and rewarding read in its entirety — Russell goes on to explore the nature of the good life, what salvation means in a secular sense for the individual and for society, the relationship between science and happiness, and more. Complement it with Russell on human nature, the necessary capacity for “fruitful monotony,” and his ten commandments of teaching and learning, then revisit Alan Lightman on why we long for immortality.

Bertrand Russell on Immortality, Why Religion Exists, and What “The Good Life” Really Means (2024)

FAQs

What did Bertrand Russell say about religion? ›

In his book Why I am Not a Christian, he says that “religions are both harmful and untrue.” When he was asked, in a famous radio debate, how he could explain the existence of the universe, his reply was, “I should say the universe is just there, and that's all.”

What is the meaning of immortality in religion? ›

In many philosophical and religious traditions, immortality is specifically conceived as the continued existence of an immaterial soul or mind beyond the physical death of the body.

What is Russell's conclusion about the meaning of life? ›

To live a meaningful life one must abandon private and petty interests and instead cultivate an interest in the eternal.” all these things, if not quite beyond dispute, are yet so nearly certain, that no philosophy which rejects them can hope to stand.

What is Bertrand Russell theory of God? ›

After looking at a few others, he concludes that the arguments for the existence of a God are all lacking in rigor. Since Russell, famously, held that the burden of proof is on the person making a claim, the failure of these proofs leaves him with no reason to assume God's existence.

What is Russell's argument against immortality? ›

Therefore, Russell argues against life after death. For him, all that constitutes a person is a series of experiences connected by memory and habit, which are essential characteristics of the mind. He highlights that the mind is bound up with the brain and both annihilate at death.

Why didn't Bertrand Russell believe in God? ›

He always said he denied that he could prove that God didn't exist, but he thought that there was no evidence whatsoever to support the view that God did exist. Russell did think that religion was responsible for a great deal of harm.

What did Jesus say about immortality? ›

Jesus tells us we get to choose whether or not we'll spend eternity with Him: “Very truly I tell you, whoever hears my word and believes Him who sent me has eternal life and will not be judged but has crossed over from death to life” (John 5:24).

Does immortality exist? ›

While, as shown with creatures such as hydra and Planarian worms, it is indeed possible for a creature to be biologically immortal, these are animals which are physiologically very different from humans, and it is not known if something comparable will ever be possible for humans.

What is the true meaning of immortality? ›

Immortality is the indefinite continuation of a person's existence, even after death. In common parlance, immortality is virtually indistinguishable from afterlife, but philosophically speaking, they are not identical.

What was Bertrand Russell's theory? ›

Russell's Platonism involves a belief that there are mind-independent entities that need not exist to be real, that is, to subsist and have being. Entities, or what has being (and may or may not exist) are called terms, and terms include anything that can be thought.

What was Russell's religion? ›

The religion which has no dogma is greater and more religious than one which rests upon the belief that in the end our ideals are fulfilled in the outer world. Summary To the philosophers of religion, Bertrand Russell is known, above all, by his pamphlet, Why I am not a Christian.

What was Bertrand Russell's conclusion? ›

Interestingly, in his Autobiography, Russell summarizes his conclusion in Human Society in Ethics and Politics in the following manner: “The conclusion that I reach is that ethics is never an independent constituent, but is reducible to politics in the last analysis.” (523) He reiterates that there is no such thing as ...

What is Russell's moral argument? ›

Russell's moral theory, at least as he describes it in the debate, was that our moral judgments come from a combination of our nurture and education, but primarily come from our feelings and their consequences.

Did Bertrand Russell believe in the soul? ›

Answer and Explanation:

No, Bertrand Russel did not believe in souls. In Bertrand's history, he believed in death as the final event of all individuals. He also believed that the human body is a composite of events and is not just the normal body and soul.

What did Bertrand Russell say? ›

Do not fear to be eccentric in opinion, for every opinion now accepted was once eccentric. Of all forms of caution, caution in love is perhaps the most fatal to true happiness. The fundamental cause of the trouble is that in the modern world the stupid are co*cksure while the intelligent are full of doubt.

What does Russell say is the foundation of religion? ›

Russell writes: Fear is the basis of religious dogma, as of so much else in human life.

Did Russell Favour religion or science? ›

Russell is an avowed agnostic, so it shouldn't come a surprise that he views this topic from a "conflict theory" perspective. He lays out the usual arguments, but provides a nice wrap up with his lucid arguments in favor of a huminist/rational ethic.

Which philosopher did not believe in God? ›

Diagoras of Melos (5th century BC): Ancient Greek poet and sophist known as the Atheist of Milos, who declared that there were no Gods. Denis Diderot (1713–1784): editor-in-chief of the Encyclopédie. Theodore Drange (1934–): American philosopher of religion and Professor Emeritus at West Virginia University.

What are some arguments for the existence of God that Russell rejected? ›

Bertrand Russell rejected the three Classical Proofs of the Existence of God: Cosmological Argument. Teleological Argument. Ontological Argument.

Top Articles
Gundam Turn Alpha IC
123Movies-Samba Traoré (1993)-watch -ONLINE-Full-Movie-HD-Free #26187
Artem The Gambler
Overton Funeral Home Waterloo Iowa
jazmen00 x & jazmen00 mega| Discover
Spn 1816 Fmi 9
Http://N14.Ultipro.com
Occupational therapist
Bin Stores in Wisconsin
Obituary (Binghamton Press & Sun-Bulletin): Tully Area Historical Society
Apply A Mudpack Crossword
Flat Twist Near Me
Draconic Treatise On Mining
Wmlink/Sspr
Southland Goldendoodles
Aquatic Pets And Reptiles Photos
Costco Gas Foster City
Ts Lillydoll
Boston Gang Map
Busted News Bowie County
Coomeet Premium Mod Apk For Pc
8000 Cranberry Springs Drive Suite 2M600
Rapv Springfield Ma
Jesus Revolution Showtimes Near Regal Stonecrest
Evil Dead Rise Showtimes Near Sierra Vista Cinemas 16
Spectrum Outage in Queens, New York
Scott Surratt Salary
UAE 2023 F&B Data Insights: Restaurant Population and Traffic Data
Best Restaurants Ventnor
Publix Coral Way And 147
Warn Notice Va
Ravens 24X7 Forum
Upstate Ny Craigslist Pets
Craigslist Org Sf
Empire Visionworks The Crossings Clifton Park Photos
Can You Buy Pedialyte On Food Stamps
Sukihana Backshots
Torrid Rn Number Lookup
Best Restaurants West Bend
Traumasoft Butler
Weather In Allentown-Bethlehem-Easton Metropolitan Area 10 Days
Rush Copley Swim Lessons
Marcal Paper Products - Nassau Paper Company Ltd. -
Tom Kha Gai Soup Near Me
26 Best & Fun Things to Do in Saginaw (MI)
Vci Classified Paducah
Grace Family Church Land O Lakes
The top 10 takeaways from the Harris-Trump presidential debate
Edict Of Force Poe
Nkey rollover - Hitta bästa priset på Prisjakt
Tamilblasters.wu
Latest Posts
Article information

Author: Nathanael Baumbach

Last Updated:

Views: 6175

Rating: 4.4 / 5 (75 voted)

Reviews: 90% of readers found this page helpful

Author information

Name: Nathanael Baumbach

Birthday: 1998-12-02

Address: Apt. 829 751 Glover View, West Orlando, IN 22436

Phone: +901025288581

Job: Internal IT Coordinator

Hobby: Gunsmithing, Motor sports, Flying, Skiing, Hooping, Lego building, Ice skating

Introduction: My name is Nathanael Baumbach, I am a fantastic, nice, victorious, brave, healthy, cute, glorious person who loves writing and wants to share my knowledge and understanding with you.